1Department of Philosophy, University of St Andrews, St Andrews, United Kingdom
2Ethics and Knowledge, World Health Organization, Geneva, Switzerland
3Institute of Ethics, History and Theory of Medicine, Ludwig-Maximilians-University Munich, Munich, Germany
©2018, Korean Society of Epidemiology
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Research question 1: What are the ethical issues surrounding healthcare for pregnant women that arise in the context of epidemic outbreaks?
Research question 2: Which steps should be taken to mitigate or solve ethical issues that fall under research question 1?
Central concept | Search strategies |
---|---|
Ethics | ("ethics"[MeSH Terms] OR "morals"[MeSH Terms] OR "human rights"[MeSH Terms] OR "government regulation"[MeSH Terms] OR ethic*[Text Word] OR bioethic*[Text Word] OR moral*[Text Word] OR "reproductive right"[Text Word] OR "reproductive rights"[Text Word] OR "human right"[Text Word] OR "human rights"[Text Word] OR justice[Text Word] OR "Helsinki Declaration"[Text Word] OR "Hippocratic Oath"[Text Word] OR governance[Text Word]) AND |
Pregnancy | ("pregnancy"[MeSH Terms] OR "abortion, induced"[MeSH Terms] OR "abortion, spontaneous"[MeSH Terms] OR "abortion applicants"[MeSH Terms] OR "reproductive health services"[MeSH Terms] OR "reproductive behavior"[MeSH Terms] OR "family planning policy"[MeSH Terms] OR "maternal exposure"[MeSH Terms] OR "maternal death"[MeSH Terms] OR "fetus"[MeSH Terms] OR "fetal mortality"[MeSH Terms] OR "congenital abnormalities"[MeSH Terms] OR "maternal fetal relations"[MeSH Terms] OR pregnan*[Text Word] OR childbearing[Text Word] OR fetal[Text Word] OR foetal[Text Word] OR fetus[Text Word] OR foetus[Text Word] OR contracepti*[Text Word] OR "family planning"[Text Word] OR miscarriage[Text Word] OR abortion[Text Word] OR matern*[Text Word] OR neonat*[Text Word] OR fertility[Text Word] OR perinatal[Text Word] OR antenatal[Text Word] OR prenatal[Text Word] OR postnatal[Text Word] OR birth[Text Word] OR obstetric*[Text Word]) AND |
Epidemic outbreak | (disease outbreak[MeSH Terms] OR communicable disease, emerging[MeSH Terms] OR epidemic*[Text Word] OR pandemic*[Text Word] OR outbreak*[Text Word] OR "health emergency"[Text Word] OR "health emergencies"[Text Word]) |
Themes | Codes | Subcodes (examples; full list as supplementary material) |
---|---|---|
Risks of misguided judgement related to systematic uncertainty in medical decision-making | Risks related to diagnosis in pregnant women | Risk that pregnancy complications give similar symptoms as the epidemic (e.g., Ebola virus disease) |
Risks related to prevention and treatment of infected pregnant women | Risk of lacking standards or guidance on when an investigational drug can and/or should be used in pregnant women | |
Risks of misjudgements related to systematic uncertainty in policy decision-making and guideline development | Risks related to the appropriate design or lack of individual hospital preparedness plans | Risk that one cannot anticipate women's treatment choices in epidemics, which complicates the development of effective preparedness plans |
Risk related to lack of evidence on technical aspects | Risk that there is limited evidence on the effects of a given epidemic on pregnant women and their fetuses | |
Risk related to lack of guidance/answers on normative questions | Risks related to unclarity to what extent policies for the prevention of mother-to-child transmission may influence or interfere with women's reproductive choices | |
Issues of harm affecting pregnant women | Issues of increased harms (mortality, morbidity) caused by insufficient access to health services in epidemics | Risk that prevention of mother-to-child transmission is focused only on the well-being of the infant, noton the mother |
Risks of increased harms (mortality, morbidity) caused by inadequate provision of health services in epidemics | Risk that during an epidemic, protective equipment makes it more difficult to deliver obstetric services safely | |
Risk of harming infected mothers through stigmatization and criminalization | Risk that mandatory testing and programmes for the prevention of mother-to-child transmission do not ensure confidentiality, causing stigma and discrimination | |
General risks of harm caused by pregnancy in epidemics | Risk that pregnancy can aggravate a pre-existing infection with an epidemic | |
Risks of harming women of reproductive age | Risks of increased harms caused by (organization of) screening in epidemics | Risk that due to privacy breaches after screening, a woman of reproductive age experiences domestic violence |
Risk of stigmatization and persecution | Risk that public discourse singles out women as sources of transmission, when in fact men are drivers in transmission, too | |
Increased risk of infection for women of reproductive age | Risk that because healthcare professionals are traditionally woman, transmission risks for healthcare professionals affect women disproportionately | |
Risks of men violence as a reaction to preventive measures | Risk that intra-marital sexual violence increases because the woman is perceived to fear contracting an epidemic from her partner | |
Issues of harming the child | Issues of infecting the child with the epidemic disease | Risk that the epidemic contributes to infections, congenital disorders, disabilities, miscarriages, etc |
General issues arising as a consequence of the epidemic | Risk that a child will be born to infected parents who will pass away or be unable to raise the child | |
Issues of harming healthcare professionals | Conflict between health care workers’protective rights and the public health need for their services in emergencies | |
Issues of harming the public/public health | Risk that infected pregnant women act as a catalyst, transmitting the epidemic to other parts of the population | |
Issues regarding pregnant women’s autonomous decisions being compromised | Risks of medical factors compromising autonomy or autonomous decisions | Risk that infection renders the pregnant women unable (at least temporarily) to make decisions |
Issues of direct interference by others | Risk that a pregnant woman’s choices about diagnosis and/or treatment are not respected | |
Issues of indirect interference | Conflict between a woman's wish to use contraceptives vs. religious values which do not allow them | |
Risks that inadequate counselling about reproductive choices and maternal care precludes informed autonomous decision-making | Risk that pregnant women do not receive enough counselling on the safety of a vaccine to make a proper risk assessment | |
Risks related to the effectiveness of sexually transmitted disease epidemic control strategies | Risk that a control strategy for an epidemic includes an unrealistic degree of abstaining | |
Risks related to the effectiveness of mother-to-child transmission programmes | Risk that prevention of mother-to-child transmission programmes are not accompanied by adequate counselling |
Themes | Codes | Proposed management strategies (examples; full list as supplementary material) |
---|---|---|
Risks of misjudgments related to systematic uncertainty in policy decision-making and guideline development | Risks related to the appropriate design of individual hospital preparedness plans | Determining preemptive, transparent, and ethically sound preparedness, distribution and triage plans |
Risk related to lack of answers on normative questions | Loosening any necessary restrictions on individual rights as soon as the epidemic is over | |
Issues of harm affecting pregnant women | Issues of increased harm (mortality, morbidity) caused by insufficient access to health services in epidemics | Avoiding 'first come, first serve'procedures and distributing services randomly among equally prioritized groups |
Risks of increased harm (mortality, morbidity) caused by inadequate provision of health services in epidemics | Facilitating the use and distribution of unlicensed antivirals for patients affected by resistant strains | |
Risk of harming infected mothers through stigmatization and criminalization | If mother-to-child transmission is identified: considering the possibility that some pregnancies are not intended | |
General risks of harm caused by pregnancy in epidemics | Recognizing special risks for pregnant women in the epidemic and prioritizing resources accordingly | |
Risks of harming women of reproductive age | Increased risk of infection for women of reproductive age | Accepting donations to assisted reproductive technologies only from seronegative individuals |
Issues of harming the child | Close collaboration between obstetrics and neonatology to optimize both maternal and neonatal outcomes | |
Issues of harming healthcare professionals | Providing vaccines to healthcare workers | |
Issues regarding pregnant women's autonomous decisions being compromised | Risks of medical factors compromising autonomy | Seeking and respecting advance directives that state preferences about end-of-life care and the fetal outcome |
Issues of direct interference by others | Liberalizing abortion laws and regarding some infections as sufficient grounds for termination of pregnancy | |
Issues of indirect interference | Communicating the papal stance that the protective value of contraceptives can legitimize their use | |
Risks that inadequate counselling about reproductive choices and maternal care precludes informed autonomous decision-making | Providing pregnant women with counseling and easy-to-understand information on vaccines and treatment options | |
Risks related to the effectiveness | Promoting faithfulness and partner reduction |